Systemic Racism: Two Views
Very roughly, when people talk about "the system" (or the structure of society), they often have in mind the interconnected policies, practices and attitudes that guide our lives, shape our institutions, determine our opportunities, and influence socio-economic outcomes.1 For simplicity, I'll talk about three aspects of a social system: "policies, practices, and attitudes." These things are at play in areas of society like education, housing, media, criminal justice, government, the labor market, and so on.2
With that in mind, here is a very vague take on systemic racism that will serve as a point of departure for further elaboration:
"Systemic Racism" refers to a society with widespread racist policies, practices, attitudes and outcomes.
Notice two things about this definition. First, "systemic racism" does not refer to a society where each and every policy, practice, attitude and outcome is racist. Instead, systemic racism might refer to a society with enough racist polices, practices, attitudes and outcomes––enough to create widespread inequalities and adversities for, say, people of Color. The general idea is that a social system can vary in the extent to which it embodies racism. Second, while this is a helpful starting point, this definition raises an obvious question: when do policies, practices, attitudes and outcomes count as racist? A more helpful definition of systemic racism should fill in the details.
This leads to an important debate in philosophy: structuralism vs. agentialism
View 1: Structuralism
With this in mind, a structuralist might be sympathetic to a simple definition of systemic racism like this 3:
The structuralist view: "systemic racism" refers to a society with widespread policies, practices, and attitudes that are responsible for creating chronic inequalities and adversities for a particular racial group.4
On some versions of structuralism, the focus is on the unequal power dynamics or oppressive relations between racial groups. As philosopher Sally Haslanger argues, some types of social systems are inherently unjust due to illegitimate imbalances in power, even if those systems are introduced with good intentions, and even if the individuals with the most power are good-willed. For example, a benevolent Monarchy is still an unjust social system. Hence, on some versions of structuralism, societies (or polices/practices) that sustain unjust power balances between Black and white people are racist, even if they are comprised of good-willed whites (or even if they––the policies and practices––are introduced with good intentions). The focus for these sorts of structuralists is not on just any type of inequality. Nor is the focus on just any policy or practice that leads to inequality. Rather, the focus is on inequalities, policies, and practices that are implicated in oppressive relations and imbalances of power (see Dustin Crummett's really helpful essay on systemic racism for a closer look at all this).
This leads to an important point about structuralism: structuralists deny that racist intentions are necessary for racist policies, practices and outcomes. Well-intentioned policies can still be racist. Here's an example that structuralists might cite. Consider homeownership and mortgage loans. Permitted by State and Federal policies, and guided by their own set of best practices, many banks and credit unions routinely disadvantage Black Americans. Part of the reason is that many banks and credit unions don't offer feasible mortgage loans for low-income Americans, a disproportionate number of whom are African Americans. Hence, a disproportionate number of African Americans fail to qualify for the right sorts of mortgage loans that would allow them to buy a house. These practices likely perpetuate inequalities in homeownership between Black and white individuals and hurt Black social mobility. Still, many of these banks, credit unions and online lenders may have no racial animosity or ill-will motivating their practices. They may be interested in maximizing profits, in taking care of their investors, and in providing a service to the general public. Moreover, Federal policies aimed at helping citizens build assets (e.g., homeownership subsidies) disproportionately benefit white individuals as compared to Black and Hispanic individuals. For the structuralist, the disadvantaging impact of these political and institutional practices may count as a form of racism (and contribute to making the U.S. systemically racist), whether or not the institutions and persons implementing these practices have racist intentions.
The strongest versions of structuralism reserve the concept of "racism" for systems alone (call this view "strong structuralism"). The idea, according to strong structuralism, is that, while individuals may have race-based prejudice, only systems count as racist. Robin DiAngelo expresses this view when she writes: "Racism is a system....Racism differs from individual racial prejudice and racial discrimination in the historical accumulation and ongoing use of institutional power and authority to support the prejudice and to systematically enforce discriminatory behaviors..." 5
View 2: Agentialism
On a contrasting view known as agentialism, policies, practices, and outcomes are racist only if they "express" the racism of individual agents (or groups of agents). Compare: racist attitudes are often expressed through actions. A hiring committee passes over Sam's application because they harbor racist beliefs about her. The committee's decision expresses their racism. The agentialist is saying something similar about policies, practices, and the outcomes they create: racist attitudes can find expression in each of these things. For example, if racist attitudes (unconscious or otherwise) lead law makers to craft policies that disadvantage people of Color, or if racist attitudes lead law makers to overlook the needs of people of Color, those policies and their outcomes express the racism of the policy makers. Alternatively, if unconscious racist attitudes lead voters to be indifferent about policies and outcomes that harm people of Color, the endurance of those harmful policies and outcomes is an expression of racist indifference in society. Yet the agentialist goes further: these types of cases represent the only way for policies and practices to count as racist. Put loosely, systems become racist when (and only when) the racism of individuals "infects" the policies, outcomes, and practices of the system (for more on this, see philosopher Tommie Shelby on racism). Racism must trickle up from individuals to institutions and systems.
To be clear, agentialists aren't saying that this is the only way for systems to become inequitable or disadvantaging. The agentialist recognizes that policies can create inequity and disadvantage. However, unlike the structuralist, the agentialist is saying that inequitable, disadvantaging policies are not sufficient for racism (though they still might be bad policies). Agentialists are making a conceptual claim: the concept of racism should only apply to systems that have been "infected" with the racism of individuals. That is, agentialists think we should reserve the concept of racism for things that can be traced back to racist agents––specifically, we should reserve the concept of racism for things that can be traced back to racial indifference, racial bias, racist ideology, or, more strongly, racial animosity. Without the influence or support of racist attitudes or ideas, a racially unequal system might be unfair, but it would not, as a matter of conceptual fact, be racist.
With this in mind, an agentialist might offer a definition of systemic racism like this:
The agentialist view: "systemic racism" refers to a society with widespread norms, practices, and racist attitudes that are responsible for creating chronic inequalities and adversities for a particular racial group (e.g., people of Color) and the relevant norms and practices have their genesis in racist attitudes or are sustained/legitimized by racist attitudes.
Importantly, agentialists claim that norms, practices and inequalities themselves can continue to embody the racism of agents even after the original agents who put them in place or supported them are no longer around. So long as racist decisions were key in shaping disadvantaging policies and outcomes, the racism of the original agents continues to infect the system. For example, consider Black-white inequalities in wealth and homeownership. To a large degree, these inequalities can be traced to intentionally racist housing policies implemented by Federal and State governments throughout the 20th century. 6 Even though the Fair Housing Act of 1969 put an end to these discriminatory housing policies, the adverse outcomes linger. For agentialists, these sorts of unequal outcomes bear the mark of racism and thereby contribute to making the U.S. a systemically racist society.
Two Final Points
Conclusion
To wrap things up, Structuralists emphasize outcome in their definition of systemic racism. Agentialists emphasize etiology. Structuralists link their definition to inequitable impact or oppressive relations. Agentialists link their definition to individuals that "infect." Agentialists ask, "was this inequitable policy crafted with racist intent?" Structuralists ask, "does this policy have an adverse and inequitable impact?" Agentialists might ask, "are these Black-white inequalities legitimized and overlooked because of unconscious bias and white indifference?" Structuralists, on the other hand, do not anchor the concept of systemic racism in the bias, racism, or indifference of white people, though they agree that white bias and indifference adds to the problem.
A structuralist might ask an agentialist: "Why does it matter whether inequitable policies and outcomes can be traced to white bias, racist ideology, or white indifference? Such policies and outcomes are chronically disadvantaging to Black people. What better language to convey both the badness and the systemic nature of this race-based disadvantage than 'systemic racism'?" An agentialists might ask a structuralist: "If we apply the concept 'racism' to any type of racially disadvantaging policy, practice, or outcome, aren't we implying that inadvertent and unintentional disadvantage could be a form of injustice? If so, that seems wrong. Tornadoes inadvertently and unintentionally create disadvantage, but they don't create injustice. Also, how do we distinguish between different kinds of racial disadvantage if the structuralist view is right? Policies that are intentionally crafted to subordinate Black people (or are left in place because of white indifference toward Black people) are morally egregious in a manner that accidentally harmful policies aren't. We need our language to convey that distinction, no?"
Examples of structuralists include:
In philosophy: Sally Haslanger and Andrew Peirce .8 In activist literature: Ibram X. Kendi and Robin DiAngelo.
Examples of agentialists include:
In philosophy: Tommie Shelby, J. L. A. Garcia, and Megan Mitchell. In activist literature: I seriously don't know...Structuralism is in vogue amongst activists.
1. FOOTNOTE ↩ When talking about systemic racism, its important to think about the nature of norms. Norms usually come in two varieties: legal-political norms + social norms. Legal-political norms are things like educational policy, tax policy, criminal law, public assistance policies, housing ordinances, health-care policy, and so on. Social norms, on the other hand, are not like legal or political norms because they do not have the backing of legal sanctions from the State. Still, social norms are powerful. They are upheld by social mechanisms that reward and punish people depending on how well they conform to these norms. Social norms are things like implicit assumptions and expectations regarding the gendered division of labor, regarding which kinds of groups are best fit for certain kinds of jobs (e.g., men for politics, women for caretaking), regarding beauty standards, regarding how to do good business (e.g., maximize profits), regarding the value and structure of the family, regarding the sorts of people that are trustworthy and would make good neighbors, regarding whose futures matter (e.g., "criminal futures don't matter"), regarding proper social etiquette (leading many minorities to "code switch" regularly), and so on. I also include institutional practices in the category of "social norms," though nothing major turns on this. Importantly, the authority of political and social norms does not apply to individuals alone. Their authority also governs corporations and institutions like schools, universities, banks, families, businesses, courts, public services, local neighborhoods, and so on.
2. FOOTNOTE ↩ See the Brown Center for the Study of Race and Ethnicity in America.
5. FOOTNOTE↩ See DiAngelo, White Fragility. For a related view, see Beverly Daniel Tatum, Why Are All the Black Kids Sitting Together in the Cafeteria?
6 FOOTNOTE↩ See Rothstein, The Color of Law, and Massey and Denton, American Apartheid.
7. FOOTNOTE↩ See Haslanger, "Oppressions: Racial and Other," and Lichtenberg, "Racism in the Head, Racism in the World."
what drives individuals to commit racism? the strange thing is that there are those who call for racism even though it is a violation
ReplyDelete